简介
首页

The Soul of Man

CHAPTER 2
关灯
护眼
字体:
上一章    回目录 下一章

‘know thyself’ was written over the portal of the antique world. over the portal of the new world, ‘be thyself’ shall be written. and the message of christ to man was simply ‘be thyself.’ that is the secret of christ.

when jesus talks about the poor he simply means personalities, just as when he talks about the rich he simply means people who have not developed their personalities. jesus moved in a community that allowed the accumulation of private property just as ours does, and the gospel that he preached was not that in such a community it is an advantage for a man to live on scanty, unwholesome food, to wear ragged, unwholesome clothes, to sleep in horrid, unwholesome dwellings, and a disadvantage for a man to live under healthy, pleasant, and decent conditions. such a view would have been wrong there and then, and would, of course, be still p. 24more wrong now and in england; for as man moves northward the material necessities of life become of more vital importance, and our society is infinitely more complex, and displays far greater extremes of luxury and pauperism than any society of the antique world. what jesus meant, was this. he said to man, ‘you have a wonderful personality. develop it. be yourself. don’t imagine that your perfection lies in accumulating or possessing external things. your affection is inside of you. if only you could realise that, you would not want to be rich. ordinary riches can be stolen from a man. real riches cannot. in the treasury-house of your soul, there are infinitely precious things, that may not be taken from you. and so, try to so shape your life that external things will not harm you. and try also to get rid of personal property. it involves sordid preoccupation, endless industry, continual wrong. personal p. 25property hinders individualism at every step.’ it is to be noted that jesus never says that impoverished people are necessarily good, or wealthy people necessarily bad. that would not have been true. wealthy people are, as a class, better than impoverished people, more moral, more intellectual, more well-behaved. there is only one class in the community that thinks more about money than the rich, and that is the poor. the poor can think of nothing else. that is the misery of being poor. what jesus does say is that man reaches his perfection, not through what he has, not even through what he does, but entirely through what he is. and so the wealthy young man who comes to jesus is represented as a thoroughly good citizen, who has broken none of the laws of his state, none of the commandments of his religion. he is quite respectable, in the ordinary sense of that extraordinary word. jesus says p. 26to him, ‘you should give up private property. it hinders you from realising your perfection. it is a drag upon you. it is a burden. your personality does not need it. it is within you, and not outside of you, that you will find what you really are, and what you really want.’ to his own friends he says the same thing. he tells them to be themselves, and not to be always worrying about other things. what do other things matter? man is complete in himself. when they go into the world, the world will disagree with them. that is inevitable. the world hates individualism. but that is not to trouble them. they are to be calm and self-centred. if a man takes their cloak, they are to give him their coat, just to show that material things are of no importance. if people abuse them, they are not to answer back. what does it signify? the things people say of a man do not alter a man. he is what he is. p. 27public opinion is of no value whatsoever. even if people employ actual violence, they are not to be violent in turn. that would be to fall to the same low level. after all, even in prison, a man can be quite free. his soul can be free. his personality can be untroubled. he can be at peace. and, above all things, they are not to interfere with other people or judge them in any way. personality is a very mysterious thing. a man cannot always be estimated by what he does. he may keep the law, and yet be worthless. he may break the law, and yet be fine. he may be bad, without ever doing anything bad. he may commit a sin against society, and yet realise through that sin his true perfection.

there was a woman who was taken in adultery. we are not told the history of her love, but that love must have been very great; for jesus said that her sins were forgiven her, p. 28not because she repented, but because her love was so intense and wonderful. later on, a short time before his death, as he sat at a feast, the woman came in and poured costly perfumes on his hair. his friends tried to interfere with her, and said that it was an extravagance, and that the money that the perfume cost should have been expended on charitable relief of people in want, or something of that kind. jesus did not accept that view. he pointed out that the material needs of man were great and very permanent, but that the spiritual needs of man were greater still, and that in one divine moment, and by selecting its own mode of expression, a personality might make itself perfect. the world worships the woman, even now, as a saint.

yes; there are suggestive things in individualism. socialism annihilates family life, for instance. with the p. 29abolition of private property, marriage in its present form must disappear. this is part of the programme. individualism accepts this and makes it fine. it converts the abolition of legal restraint into a form of freedom that will help the full development of personality, and make the love of man and woman more wonderful, more beautiful, and more ennobling. jesus knew this. he rejected the claims of family life, although they existed in his day and community in a very marked form. ‘who is my mother? who are my brothers?’ he said, when he was told that they wished to speak to him. when one of his followers asked leave to go and bury his father, ‘let the dead bury the dead,’ was his terrible answer. he would allow no claim whatsoever to be made on personality.

and so he who would lead a christlike life is he who is perfectly and absolutely himself. he may be a p. 30great poet, or a great man of science; or a young student at a university, or one who watches sheep upon a moor; or a maker of dramas, like shakespeare, or a thinker about god, like spinoza; or a child who plays in a garden, or a fisherman who throws his net into the sea. it does not matter what he is, as long as he realises the perfection of the soul that is within him. all imitation in morals and in life is wrong. through the streets of jerusalem at the present day crawls one who is mad and carries a wooden cross on his shoulders. he is a symbol of the lives that are marred by imitation. father damien was christlike when he went out to live with the lepers, because in such service he realised fully what was best in him. but he was not more christlike than wagner when he realised his soul in music; or than shelley, when he realised his soul in song. there is no one type for man. p. 31there are as many perfections as there are imperfect men. and while to the claims of charity a man may yield and yet be free, to the claims of conformity no man may yield and remain free at all.

individualism, then, is what through socialism we are to attain to. as a natural result the state must give up all idea of government. it must give it up because, as a wise man once said many centuries before christ, there is such a thing as leaving mankind alone; there is no such thing as governing mankind. all modes of government are failures. despotism is unjust to everybody, including the despot, who was probably made for better things. oligarchies are unjust to the many, and ochlocracies are unjust to the few. high hopes were once formed of democracy; but democracy means simply the bludgeoning of the people by the people for the people. it has been found out. i must say p. 32that it was high time, for all authority is quite degrading. it degrades those who exercise it, and degrades those over whom it is exercised. when it is violently, grossly, and cruelly used, it produces a good effect, by creating, or at any rate bringing out, the spirit of revolt and individualism that is to kill it. when it is used with a certain amount of kindness, and accompanied by prizes and rewards, it is dreadfully demoralising. people, in that case, are less conscious of the horrible pressure that is being put on them, and so go through their lives in a sort of coarse comfort, like petted animals, without ever realising that they are probably thinking other people’s thoughts, living by other people’s standards, wearing practically what one may call other people’s second-hand clothes, and never being themselves for a single moment. ‘he who would be free,’ says a fine thinker, ‘must not conform.’ and authority, p. 33by bribing people to conform, produces a very gross kind of over-fed barbarism amongst us.

with authority, punishment will pass away. this will be a great gain—a gain, in fact, of incalculable value. as one reads history, not in the expurgated editions written for school-boys and passmen, but in the original authorities of each time, one is absolutely sickened, not by the crimes that the wicked have committed, but by the punishments that the good have inflicted; and a community is infinitely more brutalised by the habitual employment of punishment, than it is by the occurrence of crime. it obviously follows that the more punishment is inflicted the more crime is produced, and most modern legislation has clearly recognised this, and has made it its task to diminish punishment as far as it thinks it can. wherever it has really diminished it, the results have always been extremely p. 34good. the less punishment, the less crime. when there is no punishment at all, crime will either cease to exist, or, if it occurs, will be treated by physicians as a very distressing form of dementia, to be cured by care and kindness. for what are called criminals nowadays are not criminals at all. starvation, and not sin, is the parent of modern crime. that indeed is the reason why our criminals are, as a class, so absolutely uninteresting from any psychological point of view. they are not marvellous macbeths and terrible vautrins. they are merely what ordinary, respectable, commonplace people would be if they had not got enough to eat. when private property is abolished there will be no necessity for crime, no demand for it; it will cease to exist. of course, all crimes are not crimes against property, though such are the crimes that the english law, valuing what a man has more than what a p. 35man is, punishes with the harshest and most horrible severity, if we except the crime of murder, and regard death as worse than penal servitude, a point on which our criminals, i believe, disagree. but though a crime may not be against property, it may spring from the misery and rage and depression produced by our wrong system of property-holding, and so, when that system is abolished, will disappear. when each member of the community has sufficient for his wants, and is not interfered with by his neighbour, it will not be an object of any interest to him to interfere with anyone else. jealousy, which is an extraordinary source of crime in modern life, is an emotion closely bound up with our conceptions of property, and under socialism and individualism will die out. it is remarkable that in communistic tribes jealousy is entirely unknown.

now as the state is not to govern, p. 36it may be asked what the state is to do. the state is to be a voluntary association that will organise labour, and be the manufacturer and distributor of necessary commodities. the state is to make what is useful. the individual is to make what is beautiful. and as i have mentioned the word labour, i cannot help saying that a great deal of nonsense is being written and talked nowadays about the dignity of manual labour. there is nothing necessarily dignified about manual labour at all, and most of it is absolutely degrading. it is mentally and morally injurious to man to do anything in which he does not find pleasure, and many forms of labour are quite pleasureless activities, and should be regarded as such. to sweep a slushy crossing for eight hours, on a day when the east wind is blowing is a disgusting occupation. to sweep it with mental, moral, or physical dignity seems to p. 37me to be impossible. to sweep it with joy would be appalling. man is made for something better than disturbing dirt. all work of that kind should be done by a machine.

and i have no doubt that it will be so. up to the present, man has been, to a certain extent, the slave of machinery, and there is something tragic in the fact that as soon as man had invented a machine to do his work he began to starve. this, however, is, of course, the result of our property system and our system of competition. one man owns a machine which does the work of five hundred men. five hundred men are, in consequence, thrown out of employment, and, having no work to do, become hungry and take to thieving. the one man secures the produce of the machine and keeps it, and has five hundred times as much as he should have, and probably, which is of much more importance, a great p. 38deal more than he really wants. were that machine the property of all, every one would benefit by it. it would be an immense advantage to the community. all unintellectual labour, all monotonous, dull labour, all labour that deals with dreadful things, and involves unpleasant conditions, must be done by machinery. machinery must work for us in coal mines, and do all sanitary services, and be the stoker of steamers, and clean the streets, and run messages on wet days, and do anything that is tedious or distressing. at present machinery competes against man. under proper conditions machinery will serve man. there is no doubt at all that this is the future of machinery, and just as trees grow while the country gentleman is asleep, so while humanity will be amusing itself, or enjoying cultivated leisure—which, and not labour, is the aim of man—or making beautiful things, or reading beautiful p. 39things, or simply contemplating the world with admiration and delight, machinery will be doing all the necessary and unpleasant work. the fact is, that civilisation requires slaves. the greeks were quite right there. unless there are slaves to do the ugly, horrible, uninteresting work, culture and contemplation become almost impossible. human slavery is wrong, insecure, and demoralising. on mechanical slavery, on the slavery of the machine, the future of the world depends. and when scientific men are no longer called upon to go down to a depressing east end and distribute bad cocoa and worse blankets to starving people, they will have delightful leisure in which to devise wonderful and marvellous things for their own joy and the joy of everyone else. there will be great storages of force for every city, and for every house if required, and this force man will convert into heat, p. 40light, or motion, according to his needs. is this utopian? a map of the world that does not include utopia is not worth even glancing at, for it leaves out the one country at which humanity is always landing. and when humanity lands there, it looks out, and, seeing a better country, sets sail. progress is the realisation of utopias.

now, i have said that the community by means of organisation of machinery will supply the useful things, and that the beautiful things will be made by the individual. this is not merely necessary, but it is the only possible way by which we can get either the one or the other. an individual who has to make things for the use of others, and with reference to their wants and their wishes, does not work with interest, and consequently cannot put into his work what is best in him. upon the other hand, whenever a community or a p. 41powerful section of a community, or a government of any kind, attempts to dictate to the artist what he is to do, art either entirely vanishes, or becomes stereotyped, or degenerates into a low and ignoble form of craft. a work of art is the unique result of a unique temperament. its beauty comes from the fact that the author is what he is. it has nothing to do with the fact that other people want what they want. indeed, the moment that an artist takes notice of what other people want, and tries to supply the demand, he ceases to be an artist, and becomes a dull or an amusing craftsman, an honest or a dishonest tradesman. he has no further claim to be considered as an artist. art is the most intense mode of individualism that the world has known. i am inclined to say that it is the only real mode of individualism that the world has known. crime, which, under certain conditions, may seem p. 42to have created individualism, must take cognisance of other people and interfere with them. it belongs to the sphere of action. but alone, without any reference to his neighbours, without any interference, the artist can fashion a beautiful thing; and if he does not do it solely for his own pleasure, he is not an artist at all.

and it is to be noted that it is the fact that art is this intense form of individualism that makes the public try to exercise over it in an authority that is as immoral as it is ridiculous, and as corrupting as it is contemptible. it is not quite their fault. the public has always, and in every age, been badly brought up. they are continually asking art to be popular, to please their want of taste, to flatter their absurd vanity, to tell them what they have been told before, to show them what they ought to be tired of seeing, to amuse them when they feel heavy after eating too much, and to distract p. 43their thoughts when they are wearied of their own stupidity. now art should never try to be popular. the public should try to make itself artistic. there is a very wide difference. if a man of science were told that the results of his experiments, and the conclusions that he arrived at, should be of such a character that they would not upset the received popular notions on the subject, or disturb popular prejudice, or hurt the sensibilities of people who knew nothing about science; if a philosopher were told that he had a perfect right to speculate in the highest spheres of thought, provided that he arrived at the same conclusions as were held by those who had never thought in any sphere at all—well, nowadays the man of science and the philosopher would be considerably amused. yet it is really a very few years since both philosophy and science were subjected to brutal popular control, to authority in fact—p. 44the authority of either the general ignorance of the community, or the terror and greed for power of an ecclesiastical or governmental class. of course, we have to a very great extent got rid of any attempt on the part of the community, or the church, or the government, to interfere with the individualism of speculative thought, but the attempt to interfere with the individualism of imaginative art still lingers. in fact, it does more than linger; it is aggressive, offensive, and brutalising.

in england, the arts that have escaped best are the p. 45arts in which the public take no interest. poetry is an instance of what i mean. we have been able to have fine poetry in england because the public do not read it, and consequently do not influence it. the public like to insult poets because they are individual, but once they have insulted them, they leave them alone. in the case of the novel and the drama, arts in which the public do take an interest, the result of the exercise of popular authority has been absolutely ridiculous. no country produces such badly-written fiction, such tedious, common work in the novel form, such silly, vulgar plays as england. it must necessarily be so. the popular standard is of such a character that no artist can get to it. it is at once too easy and too difficult to be a popular novelist. it is too easy, because the requirements of the public as far as plot, style, psychology, treatment of life, and treatment of literature are concerned are within the reach of the very meanest capacity and the most uncultivated mind. it is too difficult, because to meet such requirements the artist would have to do violence to his temperament, would have to write not for the artistic joy of writing, but for the amusement of half-educated people, and so would have to suppress his individualism, p. 46forget his culture, annihilate his style, and surrender everything that is valuable in him. in the case of the drama, things are a little better: the theatre-going public like the obvious, it is true, but they do not like the tedious; and burlesque and farcical comedy, the two most popular forms, are distinct forms of art. delightful work may be produced under burlesque and farcical conditions, and in work of this kind the artist in england is allowed very great freedom. it is when one comes to the higher forms of the drama that the result of popular control is seen. the one thing that the public dislike is novelty. any attempt to extend the subject-matter of art is extremely distasteful to the public; and yet the vitality and progress of art depend in a large measure on the continual extension of subject-matter. the public dislike novelty because they are afraid of it. it represents to them a mode of individualism, an assertion p. 47on the part of the artist that he selects his own subject, and treats it as he chooses. the public are quite right in their attitude. art is individualism, and individualism is a disturbing and disintegrating force. therein lies its immense value. for what it seeks to disturb is monotony of type, slavery of custom, tyranny of habit, and the reduction of man to the level of a machine. in art, the public accept what has been, because they cannot alter it, not because they appreciate it. they swallow their classics whole, and never taste them. they endure them as the inevitable, and as they cannot mar them, they mouth about them. strangely enough, or not strangely, according to one’s own views, this acceptance of the classics does a great deal of harm. the uncritical admiration of the bible and shakespeare in england is an instance of what i mean. with regard to the bible, considerations of ecclesiastical p. 48authority enter into the matter, so that i need not dwell upon the point.

but in the case of shakespeare it is quite obvious that the public really see neither the beauties nor the defects of his plays. if they saw the beauties, they would not object to the development of the drama; and if they saw the defects, they would not object to the development of the drama either. the fact is, the public make use of the classics of a country as a means of checking the progress of art. they degrade the classics into authorities. they use them as bludgeons for preventing the free expression of beauty in new forms. they are always asking a writer why he does not write like somebody else, or a painter why he does not paint like somebody else, quite oblivious of the fact that if either of them did anything of the kind he would cease to be an artist. a fresh mode of beauty is absolutely distasteful to them, and whenever it appears p. 49they get so angry, and bewildered that they always use two stupid expressions—one is that the work of art is grossly unintelligible; the other, that the work of art is grossly immoral. what they mean by these words seems to me to be this. when they say a work is grossly unintelligible, they mean that the artist has said or made a beautiful thing that is new; when they describe a work as grossly immoral, they mean that the artist has said or made a beautiful thing that is true. the former expression has reference to style; the latter to subject-matter. but they probably use the words very vaguely, as an ordinary mob will use ready-made paving-stones. there is not a single real poet or prose-writer of this century, for instance, on whom the british public have not solemnly conferred diplomas of immorality, and these diplomas practically take the place, with us, of what in france, is the formal recognition of an academy p. 50of letters, and fortunately make the establishment of such an institution quite unnecessary in england. of course, the public are very reckless in their use of the word. that they should have called wordsworth an immoral poet, was only to be expected. wordsworth was a poet. but that they should have called charles kingsley an immoral novelist is extraordinary. kingsley’s prose was not of a very fine quality. still, there is the word, and they use it as best they can. an artist is, of course, not disturbed by it. the true artist is a man who believes absolutely in himself, because he is absolutely himself. but i can fancy that if an artist produced a work of art in england that immediately on its appearance was recognised by the public, through their medium, which is the public press, as a work that was quite intelligible and highly moral, he would begin to seriously question whether in its creation p. 51he had really been himself at all, and consequently whether the work was not quite unworthy of him, and either of a thoroughly second-rate order, or of no artistic value whatsoever.

perhaps, however, i have wronged the public in limiting them to such words as ‘immoral,’ ‘unintelligible,’ ‘exotic,’ and ‘unhealthy.’ there is one other word that they use. that word is ‘morbid.’ they do not use it often. the meaning of the word is so simple that they are afraid of using it. still, they use it sometimes, and, now and then, one comes across it in popular newspapers. it is, of course, a ridiculous word to apply to a work of art. for what is morbidity but a mood of emotion or a mode of thought that one cannot express? the public are all morbid, because the public can never find expression for anything. the artist is never morbid. he expresses everything. he stands outside his subject, and through its p. 52medium produces incomparable and artistic effects. to call an artist morbid because he deals with morbidity as his subject-matter is as silly as if one called shakespeare mad because he wrote ‘king lear.’

on the whole, an artist in england gains something by being attacked. his individuality is intensified. he becomes more completely himself. of course, the attacks are very gross, very impertinent, and very contemptible. but then no artist expects grace from the vulgar mind, or style from the suburban intellect. vulgarity and stupidity are two very vivid facts in modern life. one regrets them, naturally. but there they are. they are subjects for study, like everything else. and it is only fair to state, with regard to modern journalists, that they always apologise to one in private for what they have written against one in public.

within the last few years two other p. 53adjectives, it may be mentioned, have been added to the very limited vocabulary of art-abuse that is at the disposal of the public. one is the word ‘unhealthy,’ the other is the word ‘exotic.’ the latter merely expresses the rage of the momentary mushroom against the immortal, entrancing, and exquisitely lovely orchid. it is a tribute, but a tribute of no importance. the word ‘unhealthy,’ however, admits of analysis. it is a rather interesting word. in fact, it is so interesting that the people who use it do not know what it means.

what does it mean? what is a healthy, or an unhealthy work of art? all terms that one applies to a work of art, provided that one applies them rationally, have reference to either its style or its subject, or to both together. from the point of view of style, a healthy work of art is one whose style recognises the beauty of the material it employs, be that material one of words p. 54or of bronze, of colour or of ivory, and uses that beauty as a factor in producing the ?sthetic effect. from the point of view of subject, a healthy work of art is one the choice of whose subject is conditioned by the temperament of the artist, and comes directly out of it. in fine, a healthy work of art is one that has both perfection and personality. of course, form and substance cannot be separated in a work of art; they are always one. but for purposes of analysis, and setting the wholeness of ?sthetic impression aside for a moment, we can intellectually so separate them. an unhealthy work of art, on the other hand, is a work whose style is obvious, old-fashioned, and common, and whose subject is deliberately chosen, not because the artist has any pleasure in it, but because he thinks that the public will pay him for it. in fact, the popular novel that the public calls healthy is always a thoroughly unhealthy production; p. 55and what the public call an unhealthy novel is always a beautiful and healthy work of art.

i need hardly say that i am not, for a single moment, complaining that the public and the public press misuse these words. i do not see how, with their lack of comprehension of what art is, they could possibly use them in the proper sense. i am merely pointing out the misuse; and as for the origin of the misuse and the meaning that lies behind it all, the explanation is very simple. it comes from the barbarous conception of authority. it comes from the natural inability of a community corrupted by authority to understand or appreciate individualism. in a word, it comes from that monstrous and ignorant thing that is called public opinion, which, bad and well-meaning as it is when it tries to control action, is infamous and of evil meaning when it tries to control thought or art.

p. 56indeed, there is much more to be said in favour of the physical force of the public than there is in favour of the public’s opinion. the former may be fine. the latter must be foolish. it is often said that force is no argument. that, however, entirely depends on what one wants to prove. many of the most important problems of the last few centuries, such as the continuance of personal government in england, or of feudalism in france, have been solved entirely by means of physical force. the very violence of a revolution may make the public grand and splendid for a moment. it was a fatal day when the public discovered that the pen is mightier than the paving-stone, and can be made as offensive as the brickbat. they at once sought for the journalist, found him, developed him, and made him their industrious and well-paid servant. it is greatly to be regretted, for both their sakes. p. 57behind the barricade there may be much that is noble and heroic. but what is there behind the leading-article but prejudice, stupidity, cant, and twaddle? and when these four are joined together they make a terrible force, and constitute the new authority.

in old days men had the rack. now they have the press. that is an improvement certainly. but still it is very bad, and wrong, and demoralising. somebody—was it burke?—called journalism the fourth estate. that was true at the time, no doubt. but at the present moment it really is the only estate. it has eaten up the other three. the lords temporal say nothing, the lords spiritual have nothing to say, and the house of commons has nothing to say and says it. we are dominated by journalism. in america the president reigns for four years, and journalism governs for ever and ever. fortunately p. 58in america journalism has carried its authority to the grossest and most brutal extreme. as a natural consequence it has begun to create a spirit of revolt. people are amused by it, or disgusted by it, according to their temperaments. but it is no longer the real force it was. it is not seriously treated. in england, journalism, not, except in a few well-known instances, having been carried to such excesses of brutality, is still a great factor, a really remarkable power. the tyranny that it proposes to exercise over people’s private lives seems to me to be quite extraordinary. the fact is, that the public have an insatiable curiosity to know everything, except what is worth knowing. journalism, conscious of this, and having tradesman-like habits, supplies their demands. in centuries before ours the public nailed the ears of journalists to the pump. that was quite hideous. in this century journalists have nailed their p. 59own ears to the keyhole. that is much worse. and what aggravates the mischief is that the journalists who are most to blame are not the amusing journalists who write for what are called society papers. the harm is done by the serious, thoughtful, earnest journalists, who solemnly, as they are doing at present, will drag before the eyes of the public some incident in the private life of a great statesman, of a man who is a leader of political thought as he is a creator of political force, and invite the public to discuss the incident, to exercise authority in the matter, to give their views, and not merely to give their views, but to carry them into action, to dictate to the man upon all other points, to dictate to his party, to dictate to his country; in fact, to make themselves ridiculous, offensive, and harmful. the private lives of men and women should not be told to the public. the public have nothing to p. 60do with them at all. in france they manage these things better. there they do not allow the details of the trials that take place in the divorce courts to be published for the amusement or criticism of the public. all that the public are allowed to know is that the divorce has taken place and was granted on petition of one or other or both of the married parties concerned. in france, in fact, they limit the journalist, and allow the artist almost perfect freedom. here we allow absolute freedom to the journalist, and entirely limit the artist. english public opinion, that is to say, tries to constrain and impede and warp the man who makes things that are beautiful in effect, and compels the journalist to retail things that are ugly, or disgusting, or revolting in fact, so that we have the most serious journalists in the world, and the most indecent newspapers. it is no exaggeration to talk of compulsion. there p. 61are possibly some journalists who take a real pleasure in publishing horrible things, or who, being poor, look to scandals as forming a sort of permanent basis for an income. but there are other journalists, i feel certain, men of education and cultivation, who really dislike publishing these things, who know that it is wrong to do so, and only do it because the unhealthy conditions under which their occupation is carried on oblige them to supply the public with what the public wants, and to compete with other journalists in making that supply as full and satisfying to the gross popular appetite as possible. it is a very degrading position for any body of educated men to be placed in, and i have no doubt that most of them feel it acutely.

however, let us leave what is really a very sordid side of the subject, and return to the question of popular control in the matter of art, by which p. 62i mean public opinion dictating to the artist the form which he is to use, the mode in which he is to use it, and the materials with which he is to work. i have pointed out that the arts which have escaped best in england are the arts in which the public have not been interested. they are, however, interested in the drama, and as a certain advance has been made in the drama within the last ten or fifteen years, it is important to point out that this advance is entirely due to a few individual artists refusing to accept the popular want of taste as their standard, and refusing to regard art as a mere matter of demand and supply. with his marvellous and vivid personality, with a style that has really a true colour-element in it, with his extraordinary power, not over mere mimicry but over imaginative and intellectual creation, mr irving, had his sole object been to give the public what they wanted, could have produced p. 63the commonest plays in the commonest manner, and made as much success and money as a man could possibly desire. but his object was not that. his object was to realise his own perfection as an artist, under certain conditions, and in certain forms of art. at first he appealed to the few: now he has educated the many. he has created in the public both taste and temperament. the public appreciate his artistic success immensely. i often wonder, however, whether the public understand that that success is entirely due to the fact that he did not accept their standard, but realised his own. with their standard the lyceum would have been a sort of second-rate booth, as some of the popular theatres in london are at present. whether they understand it or not the fact however remains, that taste and temperament have, to a certain extent been created in the public, and that p. 64the public is capable of developing these qualities. the problem then is, why do not the public become more civilised? they have the capacity. what stops them?

the thing that stops them, it must be said again, is their desire to exercise authority over the artist and over works of art. to certain theatres, such as the lyceum and the haymarket, the public seem to come in a proper mood. in both of these theatres there have been individual artists, who have succeeded in creating in their audiences—and every theatre in london has its own audience—the temperament to which art appeals. and what is that temperament? it is the temperament of receptivity. that is all.

if a man approaches a work of art with any desire to exercise authority over it and the artist, he approaches it in such a spirit that he cannot receive any artistic impression from it at all. the work of art is to dominate p. 65the spectator: the spectator is not to dominate the work of art. the spectator is to be receptive. he is to be the violin on which the master is to play. and the more completely he can suppress his own silly views, his own foolish prejudices, his own absurd ideas of what art should be, or should not be, the more likely he is to understand and appreciate the work of art in question. this is, of course, quite obvious in the case of the vulgar theatre-going public of english men and women. but it is equally true of what are called educated people. for an educated person’s ideas of art are drawn naturally from what art has been, whereas the new work of art is beautiful by being what art has never been; and to measure it by the standard of the past is to measure it by a standard on the rejection of which its real perfection depends. a temperament capable of receiving, through an imaginative medium, and under imaginative p. 66conditions, new and beautiful impressions, is the only temperament that can appreciate a work of art. and true as this is in the case of the appreciation of sculpture and painting, it is still more true of the appreciation of such arts as the drama. for a picture and a statue are not at war with time. they take no count of its succession. in one moment their unity may be apprehended. in the case of literature it is different. time must be traversed before the unity of effect is realised. and so, in the drama, there may occur in the first act of the play something whose real artistic value may not be evident to the spectator till the third or fourth act is reached. is the silly fellow to get angry and call out, and disturb the play, and annoy the artists? no. the honest man is to sit quietly, and know the delightful emotions of wonder, curiosity, and suspense. he is not to go to the play to lose a vulgar p. 67temper. he is to go to the play to realise an artistic temperament. he is to go to the play to gain an artistic temperament. he is not the arbiter of the work of art. he is one who is admitted to contemplate the work of art, and, if the work be fine, to forget in its contemplation and the egotism that mars him—the egotism of his ignorance, or the egotism of his information. this point about the drama is hardly, i think, sufficiently recognised. i can quite understand that were ‘macbeth’ produced for the first time before a modern london audience, many of the people present would strongly and vigorously object to the introduction of the witches in the first act, with their grotesque phrases and their ridiculous words. but when the play is over one realises that the laughter of the witches in ‘macbeth’ is as terrible as the laughter of madness in ‘lear,’ more terrible than the laughter of iago in the tragedy of the p. 68moor. no spectator of art needs a more perfect mood of receptivity than the spectator of a play. the moment he seeks to exercise authority he becomes the avowed enemy of art and of himself. art does not mind. it is he who suffers.

上一章    回目录 下一章
阅读记录 书签 书架 返回顶部