简介
首页

Studies in the Evolutionary Psychology of Feeling

CHAPTER XVI INDUCTION AND EMOTION
关灯
护眼
字体:
上一章    回目录 下一章

we have implied throughout that we have feeling about a thing only so far as we attach on basis of past experience an experience value to the thing, as we say, “the burnt child dreads the fire.” induction, as this interpretation is termed, is so important an element that we will devote a little space to considering its rationale, development, and place in intellectual emotion.

what is the rationale of the inductive act? why should iteration lead to expectancy of reiteration? i observe that a body unsupported falls in a hundred instances, but is it not arbitrary for me then to suppose that it will fall the hundred and first instance? in fact would it not be more rational to suppose that this particular combination should be exhausted, that it was time for nature to stop? but this very reason rests on the uniformity of nature—the very law we are questioning—as experienced in the past and applied to the future; only it is a negative law of omissions, literally law of reiteration of unreiterations. thus if reason takes the law of uniformity of nature to task it can only do so by assuming it. j. s. mill in his treatment of this matter (logic, bk. iii. chap. 3, sec. 2), falls into an error. it is, indeed, true, as he says, that some occurrences repeated suggest cessation and not recurrence, as when we have several consecutive cloudy days, we expect a bright one, or having had several rainy seasons we expect a dry one; but it is plainly wrong to 283regard this, as he does, as a contradiction of the principle of uniformity of nature. on the contrary, this is a very good example of it. experience of intermittent character of bad weather in the past leads to expectancy of its re-intermittency for the future, and the oftener the experience the stronger the belief as to the nature of the still unexperienced. a negative uniformity is as much a uniformity as a positive.

it is plain that we can assign no reason for our belief in the uniformity of nature. it is simply a fact, an arbitrary fact if you will, that the more often experiences are conjoined, the more strongly we expect the conjuncture. i may imagine a body unsupported remaining stationary in the air as readily as to imagine it falling; however, i believe it will fall, and i duck my head for fear of getting hurt. not any speculative reason then, but a very practical reason, is at the bottom of this inductive tendency, that is, the conservation and progress of the organism is secured by induction as anticipatory function. the origin of induction is not then in its abstract rationality, but in its immediate utility as a life function. experience is self-adjustment through felt stimulus. once begun it grows by continual self-reference, and hence practically all experience is inductive. experience is thus a continuum, an integrating cumulating whole; and inductive experience, like all experience, arises and progresses by reason of its serviceability.

it has been implied that the inductive act arises very early in the history of experience. every psychosis is what it is by reason of all the previous psychoses in the individual and the race. psychism, while it has its points of development in individuals, must yet be estimated as a unit, as a single whole. but we have to ask whether this modification of one psychosis by another is conscious or unconscious. if some low organism have in its lifetime but two consciousnesses, must we regard the second as 284influenced in quality by the first, and if so, consciously influenced, that is, a conscious relating, an active induction as opposed to mechanical integration? is mind always self-building, or does psychosis act and react on psychosis automatically? we have maintained that all the growth of mind has been in the past, as in the present, by struggle, by severest endeavour, and hence if experience modify experience it is by conscious act. experience thus constantly connects with itself and builds upon itself, it is self-integrating, that is, inductive, in all its evolution. mind, as primarily pleasure-pain and struggle, by endeavour reaches back to itself, realizes itself, and rises upon itself.

take a comparatively simple case. a child tastes an orange, and finds it sweet, i.e., it relates the sweetness to the object, which relating is a true thinking, an active conjoining or associating. upon the presentation of another orange to the child at a later date, he identifies it as the sweet thing; he associates sweetness as to be experienced from it on basis of past associating, that is, he makes an induction. in this second orange-experience, as far as there is active conjoining of mental products, a definite adding to present percept of sweet taste as experienceable by conscious reference to former percept (taste-experience), we must recognise a genuine thought-process. the thinking consists in the joining of sensation of taste to an object, not as a present, but as a future experience, on the basis of some past experience. here is a true mediation or reasoning of inductive type, and also a true concept-process, that is, a taking together, a conscious uniting, although the product is still particular. the nearest approach to expressing this psychological process in language is to say, “this round yellow is this sweet, because this round yellow was this sweet before.” the correlating process rests upon the relating process accomplished at first experience of orange-tasting, whereby 285the taste was related to the thing tasted. this relating may be thrust upon the mind, or the mind may consciously and actively assimilate. thought in the wide sense of the term may be made to include all mediate or immediate conscious conjoining of experiences, whether the product be general or particular.

mediacy is certainly, however, accomplished before commonness is noted, which in ordinary usage is concept-making. the grouping of the particular taste with the particular sight and touch on basis of past experience does not give a general result. the mediate term of past experience of taste which the child brings up on sight of orange and applies to the present case does not suggest commonness, but constancy of experience, for at first it knows things only as identical, and not as separate, or as like or unlike. the method of this early intelligence is that of identifying, “the orange was sweet and is sweet”; and not that of common characterizing, “oranges are sweet, and this is an orange.” the child does not discriminate or understand that the object of its first experience is, by reason of this experience, no longer to be experienced; it has not attained notion of disappearance. it does not cognize the orange as one of a group or class, having as common characters roundness, sweetness, and yellowness, and from presence of round-yellow in any instance infer sweet; but it knows orange only as this particular object of past, present, and future experience. many of the early thought-experiences of children are to be interpreted rather upon this identity-method than upon the usual interpretation of true concepts. thus the child who calls every person of certain age, dress, etc., “papa,” is not thinking of a papa, or class of papas, but of the papa. this is mistaken identity: the common and like is the same, and the child requires considerable discrimination before it attains to notion of papa in general. same and not-same are discriminated before like and unlike, and 286hence young children use common names as proper. now the mental product achieved by the child, which, as expressed in words, we term the papa, may be styled a particular concept, a gathering together of sight-sensations, and associating sound- and touch-sensations with these so that any generally like group of sight-sensations enables the child to call up on basis of past experience the associated sound and touch, to expect the gentle word and caress. the child in identifying the orange, “this round yellow thing is the sweet thing,” is bringing together with a certain general force, not of common characterization, indeed, but of temporal significance as permanent grouping. animals and young children think mostly on the identifying plan; they join to and expect for a present experience what has been conjoined with it in past experience, but the object is the same, not a like one.

how then does the child come to knowledge of things as like, to form a class of oranges after regarding all oranges as the orange? pass oranges before a young child one after the other so that one only is in sight, and the child will probably know only one orange as the same continually re-appearing. the image formed will, however, be more or less composite, the mental product will be a concept-image, as being a re-inforcement and exaggeration of common characters and a suppression of individual; but for practical purposes it is still a particular concept, that is, the child applies it to the one and not the many, and does not recognise its representative nature. a general image as a group of common qualities may be thus attained before consciousness of this generality is reached.

if now two or three oranges are presented to the child at the same time, it will learn to discriminate them as separate co-existences, having characters in common, roundness, yellowness, etc.; the objects will be recognised as individuals belonging to class round-yellow things. here a general image having a general import is achieved. 287the particular characters, round, yellow, sweet, which always centred in and made up the individual orange, are recognised to have general scope in applying to many objects. groups of characters had been achieved before by particular thinking, but now by general thought groups of characters as common are formed. from the practically coincident impressions it gains the notion orange, so that it recognises new individuals as individuals, and not as the individual or single object, as in the earlier and cruder identity method of thinking. the mind now—instead of saying “same impressions, same object”—says “same impressions, like objects.” instead of making an object as a group of qualities, it makes a class of objects having the group of qualities in common. concept-forming is thus often but an extension from what i have termed the particular concept; the group of qualities formed as characterizing the thing is through experience with co-existences predicated of things. notion or idea of the orange precedes notion or idea of orange; but both are truly notions or concepts, a taking together of impressions, one of particular, the other of general import. the general significance of the particular group is first forced upon the mind by experience, but soon the mind generalizes as well as notices generalizations brought to it. gradually the mind obtains power to generalize, not only from co-existences, but from successions, and later still to generalize by abstraction, to compare and pick out common features amidst the unlike, to search for unity in diversity.

the rise of generalizing power is through the struggle for existence; it originates, like all other mental processes, in practical needs. law is thereby not simply acted upon or merely recognised, as in the associative stage: it is definitely sought for and applied. art arises, and also science. the ability, given by generalizing power, of dealing with things in the lump, becomes of signal service, and specially distinguishes man. but the primary value of the 288concept in all its stages is not as a summation of experience, but as a guide for the future. through reiterated grouping the concept-group is recognised as permanent factor, so that one element of a group being given, other elements are expected through a conscious assimilation with the past experience. the concept answering to the word orange, for example, is the mental product recognising a constant co-existence of certain qualities of shape, colour, size, taste, etc., so that from occurrence of one or more we infer other or others. concepts are the inner groupings, the mental synthesizings, which interpret the outer groupings that we term laws of nature. in all this we see the inductive element in its conscious form, experience developing itself by anticipating future in terms of past.

we have now to consider briefly the psychological nature of judgment and reasoning with special reference to the inductive feature. logically judgment is any connecting, plus affirming of reality, as effected through the copula. the copula is made, not only to denote relation, but reality of relation, to express, not only the act of connecting, but also its validity for the case in hand. psychologically, judging may be regarded as any thinking, as any relating without reference to the things related, whether it be a joining of the concept “reality” to some other concept as a concept-forming process, or any joining of other elements. i have already discussed the nature of relating per se, but on the topic of judgment a word is to be said about the proposition-form. in all thinking there are the two things joined—subject and predicate in language-expression—and the act of joining, or copula in language-expression; thus all thought is capable of the proposition-form. indeed, the word-form cannot express a thinking but only a thought as a consolidated and single product, and as a sign of process. the word is a summary of process and relations, but it cannot express process as concept-forming 289or judging. the word orange signifies for the mind by symbolic and shorthand method, “thing is sweet plus thing is yellow,” etc; but as far as process happens, and not simultaneous composite representation, the process is capable of proposition-form. all relatings or joinings, even of particulars to particulars, are of the proposition-type, and i must dissent from the common view that two percepts cannot stand in subject-predicate relations. as i have before discussed, the relating of particular to particular is thinking, and to say “this sweet belongs to this yellow” is awkward indeed, but still psychologically proper. every proposition, on the other hand, is susceptible of analysis as expressive of concept-forming relating. the proposition “man is mortal” is expression of a mental process of joining; the concept mortal is either attached to or detached from the concept man, according as we consider the process as synthetic or analytic. if it be a grouping or concept-forming in full sense, it means that in forming the concept man, we add to the already gathered qualities the quality “mortal” on basis of experience. the child first notices deaths in cases of john, peter, etc., whom it knows to belong to the class “men,” forms the concept “mortal” and adds it by generalisation to the whole class and enlarges concept “man” by one quality. this proposition, as denoting inductive concept-forming, expresses the act of incorporating on basis of experience the quality mortal into the quality-group man. as analytic, as a detaching of what has been grouped, the proposition still expresses joining, and until the statement becomes purely formal and practically meaningless the rejoining is always a strengthening of the concept, and formative in its value.

all uniting or relating is, however, more than a bare connecting; it is a definite mode of relating, it has a form; and the first and fundamental form is that of time and space, by which all relating has the inductive quality of 290relying upon the past for the interpretation of the future. but thought as self-active mentality is specially stimulated and controlled by the form of reality. all relatings are not, however, influenced by sense of reality, and hence belief is not coincident with judgment in the large sense. affirmation or denial of actuality or reality is a kind of joining, but is not joining per se. the infant joins taste of sweetness with percept round-yellow for the first time and for many following times with no reference to reality or unreality. “this round-yellow is this sweet” expresses a mere connecting, a bare relating, but as neither real nor unreal. there is no emphasis laid on the copula by which it expresses more than a mere joining. but let the perfect tranquility of the child’s experience be broken in upon by discord of appearance and reality, let the child once have a bitter experience with a round lemon, then its future conjoinings of round-yellow and sweet will be more or less tinged by sense of possibility of error, and emphasis will be laid on the copula, “that is sweet.” through other such experiences with other of its thought-groups, the child generalises to the universal significance of reality and unreality for all its thinking; hence, all conjoinings with their copula-expressions attain a new force and quality from this induction. in the light of fallibility as making up a part of the concept “experience,” all thought-experience modifies itself by this self-relation. reality becomes so constant and universal for all thought-life that mature thought can never escape it. hegel tried to rise superior to the notion of existence, but psychologically, at least, he failed. the conception or induction of reality becomes a necessary form of thought by being united with all unitings. judgment in the narrow sense may be defined as all those relatings in which the reality of the relation is affirmed or denied.

lastly a word on the nature of reasoning. reasoning is mediatorial; the joining is accomplished through one or 291more mediates. most if not all thinking is by mediating; joining proceeds only upon ground or basis, whether recognised or not as such. “kings are mortal” is the language-expression of a conjoining effected either through the particular mediate term, john, or terms, john, peter, etc., or through the general mediate term men. in both cases the conjoining is effected through subjoining of the mediate term to both the elements to be conjoined. in the first case the process is: “john is mortal, john is king, therefore kings are mortal.” this relating of king and mortal is strengthened by subjoining for other particular mediates, peter, james, etc. in the second case the process is: “men are mortal, kings are men, therefore kings are mortal.” in both cases the appeal is to constancy of coherence of a quality to a quality-group, in the first, mortality coherent with king john, hence coherent with kings; in the second, kings have mortality because mortality is coherent with the group man = kings + others. in both cases the generalising tendency, that is, the inductive quality, is the main point and not the method of mediation. in both processes the concept king is filled out by the additional quality mortality, and there is real gain in generalising and concept-forming, whether the mind accomplishes it by the more special or more general reference. induction in the large sense is thus inclusive of both induction and deduction in the restricted sense as determined by the mode of mediation. inductive thinking, as we have treated it, is the joining which generalises, whatever be the means used to this end. induction as generalising tendency is imbedded in experience, and is the largest factor in all its development. all cognition as interpretation is induction.

that induction, as giving the experience value of things on basis of previous experience, is fundamental to all emotions about the things, has been implied throughout our discussion. but the inductive act may itself be 292emotively considered and intellectual emotion may arise. how and why induction came to be a pleasurable act and carried on for its own sake is, perhaps, not explainable by biologic evolution. it is certain that the inductive act, like other functions, arises as painful effort and as a mere means of serving life. identifying and recognising is accomplished only under pressure of the struggle for existence. animals in general, and, indeed, most human beings exercise their intelligence, make inductions, only as compelled by the demands of life. the australian savages who guided lumholtz in his search for new marsupials knew about the animals solely in a practical way, and were totally unable to comprehend lumholtz’s motive. so geologists examining stones are entirely misapprehended by savages and the semi-civilized, though these people are sufficiently acquainted with stones so far as they are a source of mineral wealth, are useful for building, etc. and from the point of view of natural selection pure science, the pursuit of knowledge solely for its own sake, without the least reference to its appreciation, is unexplainable.

nevertheless, it is a fact that at a certain point in psychism the intellectual life develops for its own sake; the inductive act is pleasurable, and the desire arises to continue it as such, that is, here is true intellectual emotion, an emotion arising about an intellectual act represented as such. this feeling about induction may rise to an absorbing passion, as with charles darwin. he liked nothing better than making inductions, until he finally came to like little else. if the reason is asked for induction becoming pleasurable, and an end in itself psychology at present has no answer.

it is plain that when intellectual activity is desired, not as a means, but as an end in itself, it excludes much intellectual emotion which is commonly associated therewith. surprise and wonder, for instance, are intellectual 293emotions at contemplating a conjuncture very contrary to expectation, entirely opposite to some pre-formed induction, but they do not imply devotion to intellectual activity as such. the visitor to a biological laboratory who, on first seeing blood corpuscles, cries “wonderful! who would have thought it! one’s blood all full of such things! let me look again!” is hardly actuated by the scientific motive. all phenomena are equally wonderful or wonderless—which amounts to the same thing—to the scientist; for him everything is simply natural, he forms no expectations not founded on facts. the “wonders of science” are wonders only to the outsider: the scientist takes them as matter of fact. it is no more wonderful to him that the blood should be full of corpuscles than that it should fall in drops. the tyro does not wonder at a drop of blood; he wonders to see the drop filled with myriads of animated corpuscles; the scientist wonders at neither. he who, on being told of blood corpuscles, exclaims, “i want to know,” plainly desires knowledge, but is not impelled by a pure thirst for knowledge. the scientific items appearing in the newspapers generally appeal merely to seekers for marvels and lovers of intellectual sensation. surprise and wonder are then extraneous impulses to knowledge, the impulse to knowledge for its own sake being quite distinct. as based on intellectual shock they imply a considerable intellectual integration, and hence are by no means primitive in mental life, yet far from being as late as emotion for knowledge per se. wonder gives birth to the arabian nights and to jules verne’s romances, but it always hinders true science.

again, the pleasure and desire of achieving and achievement often plays a large part in intellectual pursuits, as in a wide variety of activity. reaching an end merely for the sake of accomplishment, an emotion about any end, as, for instance, a wide generalisation to be attained, merely as end, intellectual action has in common with all 294other teleological action, but the teleologic emotion is not distinctly intellectual. the desire to achieve for achievement’s sake, to reach the satisfaction of accomplishment, is extremely multiplex in its application. the man who does a thing just to see if he can do it, who does feats of any kind is obviously impelled by a different emotion from the one who performs the same activity for the pleasure of the activity itself. he who plays a game to succeed, and he who plays for the pleasurable activity involved, are in very different frames of mind. and emotion for achievement is generally complicated by desire to be thereby superior to one’s fellows. the intense competitive struggle is plain in all departments even among scientists. the emotion of competition, the earnest desire to surpass others in interpreting nature and life is a tremendous force among all scientific workers, and not even darwin himself, exceptional though he was, could keep out every vestige of amour propre.

we note also that love of any intellectual activity for its own sake, as induction, must be distinguished from the love of truth. here induction is exercised, not for itself, but as a means to an end, truth; inducing is not merely a pleasing exercise, but a means to accomplishment of a definite result. darwin, of course, a trained and habitual inductionist, worked both from the pleasurability of the activity and from his devotion to truth, to which this induction was the true method. though both these motives, love of an activity and love of some definite end thereby attained, as truth, reputation, etc., are closely connected, they are perfectly distinct modes of emotion, as the least reflection convinces. truth is some very wide permanent and significant conjuncture of experience discovered and set forth, such as the origin of species in progressive modification, or the intensity of light in inverse proportion to the square of the distance, and this is the kind of induction or conjoining demanded by the love of truth.

上一章    回目录 下一章
阅读记录 书签 书架 返回顶部